Introduction to my translation of Husserl's Logic and General Theory of Knowledge (Hua XXX)
By
Claire Ortiz Hill
Logic and General Theory of Science
is the translation of Edmund Husserl’s Logik
und allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie edited by Ursula Panzer under the
auspices of the Husserl Archives in Cologne and published for the first time in
1996 as volume XXX of the Husserliana series. The main text of the volume is
the final version of lecture courses on the philosophy of logic and science
given by Husserl at the universities of Göttingen and Freiburg between 1910 and
1918. The course was initially entitled Logik
als Theorie der Erkenntnis (Logic as Theory of
Knowledge) and was taught in Göttingen for the first time during the Winter
semester of 1910/11. According to Panzer’s introduction (p. XIX), looking back,
Husserl characterized it as the final version of his Göttingen lectures on
formal logic. He would teach it a second and third time during the Winter
semesters of 1912/13 and 1914/15 under the title Logik und Einleitung in die Wissenschaftstlehre (Logic and
Introduction to the Theory of Science) and a fourth time at Freiburg during the
Winter semester of 1917/18 under the present title.
Panzer explains that these
lectures were considerably reworked over the years, a fact considered to be of
particular significance because those changes were made during a decisive
period in the evolution of Husserl’s thought. She notes that Husserl wrote to Georg
Misch on November 16, 1930 that, by the time his Ideas was published in 1913, he had already lost all the interest
that formal logic and all real (reale)
ontology had held for him in the face of a systematic grounding of a theory of
transcendental subjectivity.[1] And, of the very subjects
making up much of Logic and General
Theory of Science, he wrote to Hermann Weyl on October 10, 1918 that for
twenty years a central part of his lectures had been the theory of functional
judgments, of judgments with empty places, and the distinguishing of the
different modes of this empty something, and in addition, the implementation of
the fundamental distinctions between factual and formal ways of judgment,
between proposition form and proposition (or judgment), proof- and theory-form
and theory, as well as of the objective correlates associated with them. His
concept of complete manifolds already acquired in the beginning of the 1890s
had also, as had all the distinctions he had dealt with extensively in lessons
in Göttingen, proved especially fruitful. But he added that, in spite of all
that, and of all the work he had devoted to it, he had not found the time and
serenity to carry that train of thought completely to the end, because it had
had to be more important to him to develop his ideas about transcendental
phenomenology.[2]
Prepared for oral delivery in the classroom, these
lectures are refreshingly lively and
spontaneous, clearer, more explicit and readable than the books Husserl
published during his lifetime. Appendices II and III convey the enthusiasm for
logic and philosophy of science that he was intent upon injecting into his
students by means of them. There he explains that through his lectures he was
seeking to provide something entirely different from what could be learned from
books, because lectures do not in general exist for the purpose of replacing
books, or to be spoken books or excerpts from books. He warned students
that the usual expositions of logic are dangerous for beginners, because they
only too easily deaden their sense of genuine scientificity and cover up “the
difficulties from them, like chasms covered over with greenery”.
It was his desire instead to introduce them to the inmost essence of
work in logic and critique of knowledge, to the nature of their problems and
methods and prepare them to be able to derive benefit and excitement from
reading important writings in the field, something which is achieved by laying
bare the essential meaning of centuries of efforts as they relate to the state
of things at the time and its insights, by imparting an understanding of the
problems, goals, methods and a sense of the deeper meaning of the theoretical
efforts “in which the greatness, grandeur, and force of philosophical science
lies”, by teaching them to sense the inmost spirit of the intentions of logic
and theory of knowledge and to feel profoundly concerned by the fact that the
problems to be surmounted were of grave import for anyone interested in
ultimate truth and philosophy.
The only
justified task of the teacher, he declares, is to train beginners to
philosophize. If ‘philosophy’ is the word for the highest aims of
knowledge and the sciences directly oriented toward them, he suggests, then the
discipline we want to devote ourselves to is in fact first philosophy, because
it is a matter of investigations that must precede and be attended to before
further philosophizing can be contemplated in earnest. He defines his
mission as being one of raising students above the naïve standpoint and showing
them “the way to the mysterious solitudes in which one day the sphinx of
knowledge must unveil its riddle”. He says that he could also call it the way
to the “mothers” of knowledge, to the essence-principles of knowledge in terms
of its ultimate origins. Regarding these mothers, he says that he loves to
recall Mephistopheles’ words in Goethe’s Faust:
“Enthroned sublime in solitude are goddesses. Around them is no place, still
less any time”. Mephistopheles, he reminds students, had described that solitude
in a horrifying manner and tried to deter aspirants from venturing into those untrodden,
and not to be trodden, places where they would see nothing “in interminably empty
farness”, not hear their own footsteps, not find anything firm where they
rested. Husserl, however, counseled his students to be unafraid and to respond
with Faust, “Just keep on, we want to fathom it. In your nothing, I hope to
find the universe”.[3]
These lectures
find Husserl
enthusing that even though formal logic belongs
to one of the oldest sciences of mankind, everything in it is evolving; the “ossified
concepts and formulas of the tradition are coming alive again, moving, evolving”
(§19b). In Alte und Neue Logik, taught in 1908/09, he speaks of what a delight it is to
be alive and to share in striving after the greatness coming into being in those
days, which are not, as often said, times of decadence, but rather the
beginning of a truly great philosophical era in which age-old goals will
finally be met at the cost of truly heroic strain from toil, and new, higher,
goals will everywhere be held out. We in modern philosophy, he said, are no
less than visionaries (Phantasten).
We have the courage and determination of the highest goals, but we strive after
them on the most reliable paths, those of patient, constant work.[4]
When trying to answer questions that
Husserl’s philosophy has raised, philosophers of logic, science, and
mathematics often find that he seemed to assume his readers to be in possession
of facts about the development of his thought that are not found in the
writings published during his lifetime. By making available clear, explicit,
and revealing discussions of important topics less thoroughly and clearly
treated in those writings, the publication of his lecture courses is gradually
providing really significant material for putting
together a complete picture of his teachings on crucial matters. By providing
material necessary for assuring that his ideas will one day have the impact on
the history, philosophy, invention, and pedagogy of modern logic, set theory,
and the foundations of mathematics that they should have had from the beginning,
these lecture courses afford needed insight into how the father of
phenomenology managed to exercise the profound philosophical impact he did on
the times that gave birth to twentieth-century philosophy.
This
particular volume is a very important link in the chain of ideas connecting
Husserl’s Logical Investigations of
the turn of the century to his Formal and
Transcendental Logic of 1929 and helps to subvert many idées reçues about the development of his thought. For instance, it
routs the widely held view that he lapsed back into psychologism after
trouncing it in the earlier work. Indeed, these lectures show him still pursuing
the course set out in that work well into the second decade of the century and
displaying utter consistency with stands he had begun taking toward, for
example, categoriality, analyticity, axiomatization, completeness, Platonism,
idealism, empiricism, logicism, manifolds, mathematics, anti-psychologism, objective
and subjective presentation, pure logic, dependent and independent meanings,
during the 1890s and which were still pursued in his latest work, topics,
moreover, that were of fundamental importance to the makers of twentieth-century
philosophy in English-speaking countries and still are to their followers (ones
enchanted by Michael Dummett’s interpretation of Gottlob Frege’s writings, for
example).
In addition to the topics just
mentioned, philosophers trained in the Analytic tradition are presently especially
well primed to appreciate a wealth of interesting
insights published
here, for example, those into (in alphabetical
order): the word ‘all’, demonstratives, existential generalization, extensionality,
formal logic,
the foundations of arithmetic, functions and arguments,
identity/equivalence/equality, imaginary numbers, logicism, mathematizing logic,
modality, philosophical grammar, philosophy of language, quantification,
relations, sense and meaning, set theory, states of affairs, theory
of inference, theory of judgment, theory of probability, truth, wholes and
parts. This is of particular significance because these subjects have long been
the bailiwick of philosophers who, loath to inquire into their own history
and to acquire the linguistic skills needed to study works unavailable in English,
have long viewed Husserl’s work through a glass darkly.
In contrast, Husserl rarely mentions
phenomenology here, to which there are only eleven references beginning in the
last third of the course. Four of them appear in the appendices. Only in §69, the very last section of the work, where
Husserl argues that a systematic phenomenology of consciousness and its
consciousness-correlates is needed to solve problem of reason, is phenomenology
considered somewhat closely. The word ‘transcendental’ is mentioned a mere
fifteen times and is so only in connection with transcendental numbers, Kantian
philosophy or to defend himself against charges that he was trying to
penetrate into a mystical transcendental world by means of his own
intellect.
The main text
of this last version of the lecture course is divided into three sections. The
first is devoted to defining and characterizing formal logic, the second to a
systematic theory of meaning and judgment, and the third to the theory of
science. It is followed by eighteen appendices of related material which
Husserl himself had designated for insertion into specific places within the
text, or individual pages which he had added to the bundle of papers making up
the text of the course. All the texts published in the appendices are from Logik als Theorie der Erkenntnis 1910/11.
Kant is the philosopher most cited here, followed closely behind by Brentano.
Only Aristotle, Bolzano and Euclid merit more than a few mentions.
Husserl states the
subject and purpose of these lectures in the first few minutes of the course. He
says that it can be designated by one word: ‘understanding’, a synonym of ‘reason’
signifying the many mental activities and achievements which span all areas of
the life of the mind and are familiar to everyone from experiences prior to any
logic. Understanding, he tells students, governs all the sciences, technical
arts and spheres of extra-theoretical life. Sciences are only truly sciences to
the extent that the understanding governs their findings, gives them form. It
is what sets norms for them, inquires into what is right, demonstrates error.
It creates the unity of theoretical knowledge out of unconnected experiences,
isolated convictions, presumptions, inferences. In all domains of nature, it
unveils the inviolable system of laws that are called the theory of the
particular field and it is owing to it that nature figures before the mind’s
eye as ruled by laws. It casts light on the darkness of the inner life and the
life of the will, judges beauty and ugliness, goodness and badness,
appropriateness and inappropriateness.
An essentially
new line of inquiry opens up, Husserl teaches, when we turn our gaze away from
the things we know through the understanding to consider the ways in which it
operates and inquire into the forms in which this takes place, which forms they
imprint upon the contents thought by means of it, which norms they are bound to
in so doing, and how reaching or missing the goal of truth essentially depends
upon the observance or non-observance of these forms and norms. He cites John Locke
who, in An Essay Concerning Human
Understanding, compared
the understanding to the eye, which while making all things knowable for
us, does not perceive itself, and only with great difficulty can make itself
its own object. He maintains that it is only in logic–whose goal it is to
acquire systematically exhaustive, purely theoretical self-knowledge of the
understanding’s ways of experiencing and of all the kinds and forms of the
thought-contents specific to it–that the understanding reflectively investigates
itself. So it is that the purpose of this course is to provide a glimpse of the
vast science that this awareness opens up and of the great importance the attainment
of this aim has for knowledge. In so doing, he seeks to introduce beginners to
great and interesting areas of logic to the extent that they can lay claim to
scientificity. The imperfect state of knowledge of the understanding, he
declares in Appendix II, explains the imperfect development of philosophy and
why dogmatic-didactic presentations of philosophy prove fruitless. There, he
cites Kant’s words in the Critique of
Pure Reason that one cannot learn philosophy, but only to philosophize.[5]
Much of this
work is devoted to an exploration of the realm of meaning, which Husserl credits
Bolzano with having sighted. Meaning, he suggests, displays an inner structure
which is amazingly regular in form and can be compared to that of a crystal.
Just as crystals have their crystal form and conform to a crystal system, he
theorizes, it is part of the essence of meanings that “they form fixed
configurations into concrete meanings such that all meaning is bound, so to
speak, to fixed crystal-configurations and only so crystallized can have
concrete being”. According to him, every judgment is itself a crystal, a
crystal configuration, a crystal structure which is the formal structure of its
components. He judges the metaphor to be apt except for the fact that in the
sphere of meaning every crystal must be from the fixed, coherent system; there is
no amorphousness that the same matter can assume (§27b).
In §19a,
Husserl importantly says that the Fourth Logical Investigation represented his
first attempt to do justice to the theory of forms of meanings as a highly
important underlying level of formal logic. In note 3 found at the end of the
Fourth Logical Investigation of the second edition of the Logical Investigations, he had lamented the fact that logic still
lacked a prime foundation, a scientifically rigorous, phenomenologically
elucidated distinction between primitive meaning elements and structures and
essence-laws germane to knowledge, because logicians had never scientifically
formulated a purely logical theory of forms. He maintained that that was why
the many theories of concept or of judgment had yielded so few tenable results.
He had concluded §13 of the Fourth Logical Investigation of that edition writing
that he hoped that the much improved study of the theory of forms of meanings
that he had hinted at in a note at the end of that section of the first edition,
and that he had expounded in his courses at Göttingen since 1901, would be made
available to a wider public. According to Panzer’s introduction (p. XXVII) the
more thorough presentation of the theory of meaning forms sketched in the Fourth
Logical Investigation is published for the first time in this volume.
In these lectures, Husserl indeed further develops ideas set forth in the
Fourth Logical Investigation. For example, §§20-21 find
him teaching students that the difference between independent and dependent
meanings is ideal, therefore a priori, and that pertaining to it is the wealth
of a priori laws which he had called “purely” logical-grammatical in the Logical Investigations. These ideas
about the distinction between independent and dependent meanings makes for
interesting comparison with Frege’s and Russell’s thoughts on the same,
something which I studied in “On Fundamental Differences between Dependent and
Independent Meanings” and “Incomplete
Symbols, Dependent Meanings, and Paradox”.[6]
All
philosophical thinking has its share of special terminology to which philosophers
are obliged to adjust if they are ever to enter into the ideas propounded
there. For example, Husserl taught that there are forms of subjective discourse
which make no reference to the contingent empirical persons investigating and
substantiating it, or for which reference to empirical-psychological facts is
extra-essential. In the sciences, he held, it is not just a question of facts
and meanings of statements, but it is also a question of insight into thinking
itself with respect to its legitimacy.
In his
discussions of these matters, he uses the term ‘noetics’, which will be
unfamiliar to some readers. He characterizes noetics as a systematically formal
theory of justification of knowledge which stands opposite to formal logic,
analytic ontology and the theory of meaning, but is attached to them in the
most intimate way. It is theory of science in the highest sense and also the
discipline that makes the ultimate and highest fulfillment of epistemological
needs possible, because only absolute knowledge can provide ultimate epistemological
satisfaction. Part of the essence of all knowledge, he maintains, is that the
Idea of the absolute “hovers” above it as its “guiding star”, so that if
philosophy is to be the name for every kind of scientific investigation aspiring
to serve the striving for absolute knowledge, then all logical disciplines, and
noetics above all, deserve to be called philosophical disciplines (§§66-69).
It is well known that Franz
Brentano taught Husserl that thinking has what he calls here the “obvious, and
therefore wonderful” characteristic of being of intentional, of being thinking
about something, which for him amounted to its having inherent meaning (§19d). He
calls this the “miracle of consciousness” and considers that for the philosophically
naïve, it seems most obvious that in subjective experiencing something can be
intended which is not itself an experience, but lies beyond the experience, and
that when it comes to such experiences subjects can be certain of the objective
validity of their intending. However, he objects, this obviousness actually
proves to be the “enigma of all enigmas”, the original one of which centers on
the original fact that each experience called consciousness has intrinsic
meaning (Appendix V).
Cognizant of the importance
of the ambiguity, the two-sidedness, of the word ‘knowledge’, i.e., the fact
that it may signify either the knowing process or what is known, as it is known,
in §7 Husserl very succinctly defines what he came to call the “noematic”
perspective as the turning toward what is known as such–toward the noema–as the
essential counterpart to noetic reflections on the forms of knowing in pure
generality from the standpoint of correctness.
In Ideas I, he was much more forthcoming
about exactly what noemata are. Explaining the need to distinguish between the
parts and phases of the intentional experience and the fact that it is
consciousness of something, he explained there that,
Every intentional experience… is
noetic, it is its essential nature to harbor in itself a “meaning” of some
sort… and on the ground of this gift of meaning, and in harmony therewith, to
develop further phases which through it become themselves “meaningful.” Such
noetic phases include… the directing of the glance of the pure Ego upon the
object “intended” by it in virtue of its gift of meaning, upon that which “it
has in its mind as something meant”…. Corresponding… to the manifold data of
the real (reellen) noetic content,
there is a variety of data displayable in really pure… intuition, and in a
correlative “noematic content,” or
briefly “noema”…. Perception… has it
noema, and at the base of which is its perceptual meaning… the perceived as such. Similarly, the recollection
has its own remembered as such,
precisely as it is “meant” and “consciously known” in it; so again, judging has
its own judged as such, pleasure, the
pleasing as such…. We must everywhere take the noematic correlate, which (in a
very extended meaning of the term) is here referred to as “meaning” precisely as it lies “immanent” in the
experience of perception, of judgment, of liking…. (§88)
Thinking as
thinking about something, Husserl teaches in these lectures, has an immanent a
priori constitution and from the noematic perspective has necessary types and
forms in which it alone can acquire a relationship to objectivity, in which it
can intend–mean–something and do so prior to any question as to whether the intending
is valid or not. The nature and form of the intentionality of thinking is
reflected in the nature and form of logical meaning, so that understanding the
basic composition of logical meaning affords insight into the a priori essence
of thinking and vice versa. The theory of forms of meanings thereby gives a
theory of forms of thinking as that of logical meaning. So the theory of forms
of logical meanings would also correlatively be a theory of forms of thinking
with respect to its meaning-like essence, with respect to the possible forms of
its intentionality. He says that studying the wonders of the intentionality of
thinking is certainly a matter of the greatest interest and that one thereby
goes about this by investigating the basic constitution of the realm of meaning
prior to all questions of validity (§19c-d).
So these
lectures contain ample information about Husserl’s theory of the essential
parallelism obtaining between the various kinds of consciousness and the
concept of linguistic meaning, thus supporting Dagfinn Føllesdal’s thesis that
with the theory of noemata Husserl generalized the notion of linguistic meaning
to the realm of all intentional acts.[7] However, the noemata must
not be too closely identified with Fregean linguistic meanings, because, as I
pointed out in Word and Object in
Husserl, Frege and Russell, for Husserl,
the
logico-linguistic realm was but a stepping stone to an infinitely vaster realm
of inquiry…. he undertook to do something that was radically different from
anything Frege and his successors ever tried, or ever considered worth doing:
he “plunged into the task of laying open the infinite field of transcendental
experience” (CM, p. 31). Not just interested in the meaning of linguistic
expressions, Husserl made it his life’s work to investigate as thoroughly and
painstakingly as humanly possible the meaning conferred upon objects by the
intentional acts of consciousness. To explain how the human mind confers meaning on its objects, Husserl posited the presence
of structures analogous to the intensional “meanings” used by his
contemporaries and predecessors in their discussions of the meanings of words.
These structures were the noemata. [8]
Importantly, it
was precisely during the years in which Husserl gave the lectures published
here that he fully developed the noematic notion of meaning, which did
not figure in the Logical Investigations.
In his 1913 Foreword to the second edition of that work,[9] he even signaled it as a
“defect” of the First Logical Investigation that the essential ambiguity of
‘meaning’ as an Idea had been not stressed, because attention had not been paid
there to the fundamental role of the distinction between the ‘noetic’ and ‘noematic’
in all fields of consciousness and to the parallelism obtaining between them,
which was only fully expounded for the first time in Ideas I published in 1913. He regretted the fact that the Logical Investigations had unduly, one-sidedly
emphasized the noetic concept of meaning and that the problem had not been
understood and remedied until the end of the work, but considered that the
distinction had nonetheless been implicit in many of the arguments of the Sixth
Logical Investigation.[10] Along these lines, Panzer
stresses in her introduction that one must above all bear in mind that Husserl
had had compelling reasons to change the title of his lecture course from Logik als Theorie der Erkenntnis (1910/11)
to Logik und Einleitung in die Wissenschaftstlehre
(1912/13, 1914/15), because it had become chiefly a matter of a systematic
theory of forms of meanings from the noematic perspective as a basic part of an
a priori, and primarily formal, theory of science, whereby the noetic theory of
justification was for the time being expressly left to the side (pp. XV-XVI).
Husserl
further instructs students that they will encounter a pure logic in a new sense
through investigating what is stated in the stating, what is known in the
knowing, as it is known, meant, in knowledge. In particular, they will first
encounter “apophantic logic”, also a term which some readers might find
mystifying and which Husserl variously defines as the logic of statements, the
logic of asserting propositions, the pure logic of affirmative statements, the
logic of the affirmative predicative proposition, which he considered to be
essentially the logic Aristotle dealt with under the heading of Analytics. Aristotle,
he notes, called judgment, the statement as such, ‘apophansis’, whose form is
symbolized by ‘A is b’. It is a mere predication in which something is stated
about something. For Husserl, pure arithmetic, the whole of formal
mathematics or theory of manifolds was for essential reasons intertwined with
the logic of affirmations and formed a higher tier of apophantics. He
considered recognizing this and characterizing them so to be of the greatest
importance philosophically (§§7, 9, 14, 15c, 19c).
In §66, he
reminds students that in seeking to obtain the first idea of formal logic, and of
apophantic logic to begin with, he had told them that sciences live on
objectively in the form of writings in which scientific theories are given
expression and that this continued existence is one of interrelated statements
having their meanings in judgments and relationships of judgments referring to the
objectivities of the scientific domain, for example, to numbers in arithmetic,
to geometrical forms in geometry, to the things of the natural world and
natural relationships in the natural sciences. He particularly examines, and
criticizes, Kant’s distinction between analytic and synthetic judgments. Kant,
he notes in §46c, had been the first to see the difference between the analytic
and synthetic a priori and had rightly called it a classic distinction for
transcendental philosophy, but he neither had a genuine concept of the
analytical as determined by the conceptual sphere of the formal categories, nor
had he understood the essence of formal logic. If, Husserl reasons, as Kant
wished, we separate the logical a priori from everything empirical-methodological,
we see that what is purely logical according to the tradition belongs exclusively
in the apophantic sphere and that therefore formal logic to a certain extent
sought to be apophantics. However, apart from Leibniz and some of those
influenced by him, neither Kant nor anyone else had suspected that pure
arithmetic and all the disciplines essentially related to it intrinsically
belong together with the old formal logic. Kant’s concept of the analytical did
not extend beyond his concept of apophantic logic. His definition of analytic
judgments is therefore limited to categorical judgments and implies that every
categorical judgment is analytic whose predicate concept is contained in the
subject concept. So Husserl concludes that, however right Kant’s observation was,
it blocked the way to the far more important realization of the fundamental
separation of everything belonging to the realm of formal category from the
sphere of the non-formal a priori, something which leads to a wholly unacceptable
equation and equal treatment of arithmetic disciplines with other purely
mathematical disciplines and the severing of both from what Kant called pure
natural science.
Husserl
explains here that by analytic truths in the broadest sense, he himself understands
“analytic concept-truths, therefore all pure categorial truths, therefore, the
entire pure mathesis, pure logic, then however, also their a priori and
empirical individuations, therefore, the analytic necessities”. For him, the
pure categorial concept-truths essentially belong together as a whole and form
a single system of scientific disciplines to be dealt with under the broadest
heading of formal logic, or analytics, or the mathesis universalis in Leibniz’ sense (§§45b, 47e, 50). In Appendix
XV, he underscores the purely categorial nature of formal logic. Instead of
formal logic, he tells his students, we can also say analytics or science of
what is analytically knowable in general, the science that establishes and
systematically substantiates analytic, categorial, laws.
Among the stated goals of
Husserl’s late work Formal and
Transcendental Logic was to redraw the boundary line between logic and
mathematics in light of the new investigations into the foundations of
mathematics and to examine the logical and epistemological issues such
developments raise. This is something that the former student and assistant of
Karl Weierstrass in Berlin, long-term friend of George Cantor in Halle, and
member David Hilbert’s circle in Göttingen undertook to do in these lectures. In
particular, he argues here that those who had mixed the roles of the
philosopher and the mathematician had only succeeded in creating their own
closed worlds. Arithmetic, algebra and analysis, he teaches, developed
independently from philosophy and must remain independent. The theory of the
analytic and traditional syllogistic logic, he maintains, is a piece of the
pure mathematics of propositions and of predicates of possible subjects in
general and as such is not the job of philosophers, but of mathematicians, who
are the only competent engineers of deductive structures. If in the nineteenth
century, mathematicians had also adopted the deductive theories of traditional
syllogistic logic and gradually developed a mathesis of propositional,
conceptual, and relational meanings in the spirit of the solely proper
mathematical method, they had only laid hold of a field that was their rightful
possession (§50).
So, according
to him here, all arguing against mathematizing logic was symptomatic of a lack
of understanding. With formal mathematics, he asserts, we do not actually enter
into an essentially new domain, but are dealing with a field of pure
concept-truths whose conceptual matter is inseparably linked to the original
matter of the logic of meaning. Owing to the work of mathematizing logicians, he
stresses, the disciplines of logical validity have reached a higher level of
technical perfection in certain ways. They have seen the essential kinship
between formal mathematics and formal logic and so have expanded the sphere of
the exact mathematical disciplines to include the new ones of formal logic by
carrying over to formal logic the same algebraic methods entirely suited to it.
However, they have lacked a scientific understanding of thinking and so remain
confused about the nature, meaning, and basic concepts of formal logic, and the
idea of a theory of forms of meanings as a discipline that by its very nature
is a comprehensive, difficult discipline prior to the disciplines of logical
validity has also remained completely beyond their ken. The philosopher’s task
is therefore one of providing a complementary reflection on the essence and
meaning of the governing basic concepts and basic laws of deductive
theories (§§50, 19a, d).
In these lectures, Husserl additionally
spells out for his students how they might convince themselves that there is
something in logic that is akin to what mathematicians have in mind when they
speak of functions. In particular, he discusses a theory of functional
judgments, which he specifically links to what mathematicians call a function,
something which he considers that, without arriving at the full descriptive
analysis of the kinds of judgment concerned, the sharp-witted Frege, had had the
merit of recognizing in his article “Function and Concept”. The empty places,
Husserl explains, are what mathematicians call arguments. Many empty places can
occur in a judgment, so that the same judgment can have several places, or
terms, of universality and several of particularity. These places can be pure
empty places as, for example, “Something or other is red”, in which a nominal
something figures in the subject position and is the bearer of a particular
function, or universal as, for example, “Everything is red”. However, as a
rule, the “something” is specified by a letter of the alphabet, as in the
arithmetic example, a + b = b + a, where two terms function universally and are
determined as the numbers a and b. Argument places are specifically nominal
forms. He states as a principle that every nominal position in a judgment-form
can become an argument place and take on the generality-forms in relation to
it. Arguments or generality positions, terms of universality and particularity
also occur in predication since nouns can occur there in many different ways.
Everything formal, he stresses, is exclusively composed of terms of this kind.
He considers the empty something to be of the greatest importance for the
theory of meaning and all of formal logic. As what is specifically mathematical
in the mathesis, specifically formal in formal logic, absolute emptiness of
content was for him the hallmark of the formal logical. These ideas about functional
propositions are expounded in §§26a-b, 32c, 40b-45a and Appendix XIII.[11]
This is a good
place to note that contrary to what is widely believed, Husserl did have a
formal language. In §19d of these lectures, he argues that the rigorous
carrying out of purely deductive theory requires one and the same method
everywhere, namely, what is called the algebraic method, and that mathematicians
are everywhere the technical experts qualified in deductive theory, whose development
to technical perfection is everywhere the requirement of exact science. In his Logik, Vorlesung 1896 and his Logik,
Vorlesung 1902/03, he set out the axioms, notation, and rules of inference
for the conceptual and propositional calculus he advocated.[12] In Alte und neue Logik, for example, he resorted to it to show that a
propositional form has blank terms, empty terms, or variables, so that one can
then say: Each system of values satisfying the propositional form or function
F(αβ…) also satisfies the function F′ (αβ…) and that that satisfying signifies
transforming ∏ αβ… F(αβ…) € F′ (αβ…) into a valid proposition, where
‘€’ is the sign for implication and ‘′’ marks the step from premise to
conclusion.[13]
Like his contemporaries in Germany, Husserl adopted C. S. Peirce’s symbols for
the universal and existential quantifiers ∏, ∑ which, unlike Frege’s, were
widely used.
In §39, Husserl
discusses the traditional talk of extensions of concepts according to which the
totality of objects that are to be subsumed under each valid universal-concept
are to belong to it as its extension. He taught that no pure concept has anything like an extension and that it is nonsense
to say that for every concept a
distinction is to be made between intension and extension. Indeed as shown by
the remarks he wrote on his copy of Frege’s “Function and Concept” available at
the Husserl Archives in Leuven, Husserl believed that there are extensionless
concepts, that impossible, imaginary, absurd concepts are also concepts. It was
in fact precisely the search to justify the use of apparently meaningless signs
in calculations or deductive thought that had led him to develop his theory of
manifolds as the third and highest level of pure logic. In the Prolegomena
§70, he called his theory of complete manifolds the key to the only possible
solution to how in the realm of numbers impossible, non-existent, meaningless
concepts might be dealt with as real ones. In §72 of Ideas I, he wrote that his chief purpose in developing his theory
of manifolds–which he likened to Hilbert’s axiom systems–was to find a
theoretical solution to the problem of imaginary quantities.
Chapter 11 of
this lecture course is devoted to a discussion of that theory of manifolds,
which nicely complements the discussions of the same in Introduction to Logic and Theory of Knowledge (§19) and Formal and Transcendental Logic (Chapter
3). Here he teaches that since the procedure used is purely formal, and since
not a single concept is used that does not arise out of the analytic sphere,
his theory of manifolds, for him the highest level of mathematics, is the
supreme consummation of analytics, the ultimate consummation of all purely
categorial knowledge (§§57-59).
As
is evident from the foregoing, Logic and
General Theory of Science is replete with insights into matters that many
philosophers have now been primed to appreciate out of enthusiasm for Frege’s
ideas. It in fact takes readers back to the place where two main logical roads
diverged during the early part of the twentieth century and affords a look down
the one less traveled by. It invites phenomenologists and analytic philosophers
alike to overcome pride and prejudice. Indeed, had not so many twentieth-century
philosophers resolved to barricade themselves behind the walls of ideological
prejudices, the
kinds of insights expounded here could have altered philosophical landscape in
English-speaking countries, so much so that history
will eventually show that logic and philosophy would have followed a different,
and better, course in the twentieth century had Husserl’s thoughts on these
matters found their rightful place alongside the works of Frege, Russell,
Carnap, Hilbert, Gödel, for example.
However,
although these lectures are
laced with pertinent lessons about matters that lived on to become the stuff of
twentieth-century logic and philosophy of science, they at the same time
draw clear epistemological and metaphysical lines between Husserl’s theories and
those that dominated in English-speaking countries. This is particularly
evident when one looks at the place Husserl accords to ideal entities here.
Indeed, he instructs his students to adopt ontological views about the reality
of essences, universals, Ideas, senses, meanings, concepts, attributes
essential properties, modalities, propositions, intensions–anything hinting of
the a priori–that are fundamentally antithetical to those that analytic
philosophers have wanted to have. He plainly
says that he completely means in absolute earnest that the recognition of ideal objects, or
Ideas, as new kinds of atemporal, supraempirical objects is the pivotal point
of all theory of knowledge and that he considers the proper grasp of them to be
decisive for all further considerations. He contends that it is imperative to
force people to concede once and for all that Ideas are genuine, actual objects
by contrasting them with the empirical objects that they see in the natural
attitude and alone are inclined to recognize as objects.
He
suggests that people who want to know what Ideas are need only point to
self-evident givens like the cardinal number series or to absolutely
self-evident statements about members of the number series, which he claims
everyone knows in a certain naïve way since they talk of numbers and do so in
ideal ways. Only philosophers, he charges, shun Ideas. He contends that once one recognizes givens like the
series of natural numbers as objectivities, one can only describe them in the
way Plato did in his theory of Ideas, as eternal, selfsame, non-temporal and
non-spatial, unmoved, unchangeable, etc.
He fully realized that what he was
claiming was “very hotly combated as being mysticism and scholasticism”, that people
trained in traditional philosophy instantly think Platonic Ideas and then such
Platonic realism becomes associated with mysticism, Neo-Platonism and a magical
view of nature, something as far removed as possible from genuine natural
science. Philosophers then recall how this merged into scholastic realism
during the Middle Ages. Anyone advocating giving ideal objects their due faces
charges of being a reactionary, mystic, scholastic, the latter two being the
strongest scientific terms of abuse of the time, in which formal logic is
vilified as being empty scholasticism, and espousing idealism for a pure logic is
left undefended (§§4, 5a, 8, 19a).
Indeed,
on December 29, 1916, Göttingen philosopher Leonard Nelson wrote to David
Hilbert that Husserl,
admittedly also originally came from
the mathematical school, but… bit by bit turned more and more away from it and
turned towards a school of mystical vision, whereby he also deadened the feel in his school for the demands and value
of a specifically scientific method. He even goes so far, after his own
lack of success with it, as to see a danger in methodological thinking and
thinks that it would ruin philosophers for whom the truth only reveals itself
in mystical vision. Even though Husserl himself remains protected by certain
inhibitions from mystical degeneracy by virtue of strong ties to mathematics
that he has not been able to cast off, one must unfortunately nonetheless note
with horror that after the school as such had torn down the bridges to mathematics
behind them, how unrestrainedly his students lapsed into every excess of Neo-platonic mysticism….[14]
In
the lectures published here, Husserl defends himself against such charges by
explaining that he was not adopting Ideas and classes of idealities out of some
desire to penetrate into a mystical transcendental world by means of his own
intellectual intuition, but rather for the same banal reason that he embraced
things: because he saw them and in looking at them grasped them himself. He
even compares ideal objects to ordinary stones found lying on the road. In
response to charges that he was espousing scholasticism, he insisted that he was
only asking for the intellectual integrity to allow what is prior to any theory,
because it is the most evident of evident facts, to count as being exactly what
it proclaims itself to be. If this is enough to have him called a scholastic, he
protests, then that is all fine and good, and he asks whether it was not better
to have integrity and be called a scholastic, or to lack integrity and be a
modern empiricist! He says that he advocates integrity and does not fall flat
on his face when labelled as a scholastic, because integrity stands the test of
time (§§4, 8).
For those
influenced by the Analytic tradition in philosophy who feel queasy about such
talk of ideal entities, it is worthwhile to note here that in Russell’s article
entitled “The Philosophical Implications of Mathematical Logic”, which is found
translated in Husserl’s notes on set theory,[15] Russell affirmed “that
there is a priori and universal knowledge”, that “all knowledge which is
obtained by reasoning, needs logical principles which are a priori and
universal”. He further wrote that “it is necessary that there should be self-evident
logical truths” and that these were “the truths which are the premises of pure
mathematics as well as of the deductive elements in every demonstration on any
subject whatever”. “Logic and mathematics force us, then”, Russell wrote, “to
admit a kind of realism in the scholastic sense, that is to say, to admit that
there is a world of universals and of truths which do not bear directly on such
and such a particular existence. … We have immediate knowledge of an indefinite
number of propositions about universals: this is an ultimate fact....”[16]
As is all too well
known, Husserlians and followers of the Frege-inspired Analytic school that dominated
philosophy in English-speaking countries during the twentieth century have not
in general spoken the same language. Fortunately, however, this translation
appears at a time when the latter have heartily embraced Frege’s thoughts and
concerns, many of which he shared with Husserl.
Both Husserl
and Frege faced the same terminological confusions and they both fought their
way through a terminological jungle to achieve conceptual clarity in spite of
them.[17] Though Frege’s choices
are now more familiar to most English-speaking philosophers than Husserl’s are,
they were often eccentric. As Russell wrote when he introduced Frege to the
English-speaking world in Principles of
Mathematics,
Frege
is compelled, as I have been, to employ common words in technical senses which
depart more or less from usage. As his departures are frequently different from
mine, a difficulty arises as regards the translation of his terms. Some of
these, to avoid confusion, I shall leave untranslated, since every English
equivalent that I can think of has already been employed by me in a slightly
different sense.[18]
For example, of Frege’s famous
distinction between Sinn and Bedeutung, Russell wrote “The
distinction between meaning (Sinn)
and indication (Bedeutung) is
roughly, though not exactly, equivalent to my distinction between a concept as
such and what the concept denotes”.[19] For his part, in these
lectures, Husserl explains his use of the term ‘nucleus’ in these terms,
the
word concept is so ambiguous and in particular <is> also used so
ambiguously in the field of formal logic itself that we cannot use it without
thinking twice. In any event, it may be said that by means of my analysis, an
extraordinarily important meaning of the word concept as “nucleus-content” has
been scientifically defined. And at the same time, the general-nucleus narrows
down the meaning of concept in a clear-cut way. It is indeed often said that
generality is part of the essence of concepts. §25)
In the First
Logical Investigation, he had written of how in the absence of fixed
terminological landmarks, concepts run confusedly together and fundamental
confusions arise, and he went on to defend his decision to use ‘sense’ and
‘meaning’ as synonyms as follows,
It
is agreeable to have parallel, interchangeable terms in the case of this
concept, particularly since the sense of the term ‘meaning’ is itself to be
investigated. A further consideration is our ingrained tendency to use the two
words as synonymous, a circumstance which makes it seem rather a dubious step
if their meanings are differentiated, and if (as G. Frege has proposed) we use
one for meaning in our sense, and the other for the objects expressed. To this
we may add that both terms are exposed to the same equivocations, which we
distinguished above in connection with the term ‘expression’, and to many more
besides, and that this is so both in scientific and in ordinary speech. (§15)
In
§42 of the Second Logical Investigation, he complained that the word ‘meaning’
was equivocal so that people did not hesitate to call the object of a presentation
a ‘meaning,’ and to say the same of its ‘intension’, the sense of its name. He further noted that
since a meaning is often called a concept, talk of concepts and objects of
concepts is also ambiguous.
And this brings us to take a look at
Husserl’s use of the notoriously hard to translate word ‘Vorstellung’, for which there is no satisfactory English
equivalent. It has very frequently been translated as ‘idea’, ‘imagination’, or
‘representation’, all words charged with philosophical connotations that are
not his. He addresses the problem in §8 stating, “One must, besides, also
surely keep in mind the fact that the word idea (Idee) has taken on many meanings and that, especially in the
parlance of English philosophy, it is an expression for subjective experiences,
for presentations (Vorstellungen),
that, however, Ideas in my Platonic sense are not presentations, but atemporal,
supraempirical objectivities”. In these lectures, he in fact uses ‘Vorstellung’ ubiquitously in ways that are unusual in the English
language. I have consistently translated ‘Vostellung’
as ‘presentation’ and can only ask readers to try to enter into his thought and
divine his meaning.
Readers should
also be aware that Husserl’s use of ‘Vorstellung’
in these lectures differs from his use of it in other periods of his career. In
his “Psychological Studies in the Elements of Logic” of 1894, he wrote that he
thought it was a good principle to avoid using a word as equivocal as ‘Vorstellung’ as much as possible.[20] Students of his logic
course of 1902/03 heard him complain that no psychological and logical term was
laden with so many pernicious ambiguities as was ‘Vorstellung’.[21] There he distinguished,
as Frege had in Foundations of Arithmetic,[22] between
subjective Vorstellungen as psychological experiences and objective
logical Vorstellungen, which he regarded as the “completely lost”
distinction that Bolzano had for the first time identified as a “cornerstone of
all genuinely pure logic”.[23] In §5 of the introduction
to the second volume of the Logical
Investigations, he told readers that he should “have to raise fundamental
questions as to the acts, or alternatively, the ideal meanings, which in logic
pass under the name of ‘presentations’ (Vorstellungen)”.
It was, he said, “important to clarify and prise apart the many concepts that
the word ‘presentation’ has covered, concepts in which the psychological, the
epistemological and the logical are utterly confused”. After discussing
thirteen dangerous ambiguities associated with the word in §§44-45 of the Fifth
Logical Investigation, he concluded that “However the notion of presentation is
defined, it is universally seen as a pivotal concept, not only for psychology,
but also for epistemology, and particularly for pure logic”.
In these
lectures, Husserl speaks of how presentation may signify something
psychological like the intuition or thought-presentation underlying the
thought-act and having nothing to do with the theory of pure meanings, something
like a mere neutral thought, or something different and mixed in with this. As
an example, he gives the fact that that nouns are said to be expressions of mere
presentations, but not complete judgments. And he recalls that in previous
lectures on logic, he had defined a different, more important, concept of
presentation. What he was presently calling nominal “syntagma”, he had called nominal
presentation and had discerned as many kinds of presentations as there are
syntagmas, thus making presentation the same as syntagma (§25).
Syntagmas in
turn are defined as: the syntactical “stuff”, which is “always given in
syntactical form that lends it the specific thought-function in the proposition
unit and overall meaning in general”. He says that he had found it necessary to
introduce an artificial word that could be used when there was a danger of
becoming ensnared in the myriad ambiguities surrounding the words ‘presentation’
and ‘concept’ and adds that if the Idea of presentation is to be appealed to in
the realm of meaning, then the natural choice for the meaning of
“presentational content” as distinct from the objectivity presented is the
nucleus (§24).
Husserl takes care to
distinguish the concept of syntagma from that of nucleus by pointing out that the
former had been defined as concerning that which “is identical, which stands
out as the same noun in a different predicative function, or as the same
predicate–but in a different function−sometimes as actual predicate, sometimes
as determining attribute”. He explains that it was by contrasting presentations
such as “similar” and “similarity”, “redness” and “red” that he had been led to
the concept of the full-nucleus. He had observed that primitive presentations
of different syntactical categories coincide in terms of a content, have the
same nucleus, which could be formed nominatively, non-nominatively,
adjectivally, relationally. In comparison, however, he saw that the syntagmatic
category clings to the syntagma. Changing the function does not change the same
noun, but makes it stand out as such. There can be both something identical and
something different in syntagmas of different category, and it is precisely the
nucleus that remains the same. The syntagmas “similarity” and “similar”, or
“redness” and “red” enjoy the same nucleus. Comparing them we find that
syntagmas of a different category have an essence-nucleus. They differ in their
nucleus-form, which is what forms the pure nucleus into the syntagma of the
particular category (§25, Appendix VIII).
Every language also
has its share of recalcitrant terms which for one reason or another frustrate
translators’ efforts to capture their precise meaning. In the case of the
German language, translators must cope with the fact that it delights in
inventing compound words. Husserl makes lavish use of his freedom to do so, and
most of his creations are not found in dictionaries. I have very often had to
resort to hyphenations which, though not elegant in English, are nevertheless easily
understandable.
In reading
these lectures devoted to the theory of science, it is naturally important to
keep in mind that the English word ‘science’ and the various words derived from
it are narrower in meaning than the German word for science, ‘Wissenschaft’, and the words that are
derived from it are. It helps to remember that these words contain the noun ‘Wissen’, meaning knowledge, or the verb
‘wissen’, to know. And, it is good to
keep in mind that the English word ‘science’ has its roots in the Latin word scientia, meaning science, and scire, to know. In §60, Husserl sheds
some light on his particular use of the term in these lectures. There he
explains that taking up the Idea of the theory of science that had served as a
guide from the beginning of the course, then
as
the formal theory of meaning and ontology described, logic is the first
manifestation of this Idea. Knowing (Wissen)
in the sense of science (Wissenschaft)
is thinking or thought-state-of-mind that refers back to thinking.
Corresponding to thinking is something thought, and so corresponding to every
science is a system of judgments in my meaning-theoretical sense, a system of
postulated truths and probabilities, and these refer to objects and
states-of-affairs. The science of meanings in general, of truths,
possibilities, probabilities in general, of objects in general in absolutely
pure, formal universality, yields a system of absolute truths to which every
science is obviously bound, and which are prior in terms of validity to every
science in general−as already to every judgment in general.
Since Husserl here takes up the
questions of logical grammar of the Fourth Logical Investigation, it is also
important to note that, as he used them, the words ‘Widersinn’ and ‘widersinnig’
do not translate neatly into philosophical English. The German word ‘wider’
means against, counter, contrary to, in opposition to. So, some have chosen to
translate ‘Widersinn’ and ‘widersinnig’ as ‘countersense’ and
‘countersensical’. Husserl himself used ‘Absurdität’ and ‘absurd’
as synonyms for ‘Widersinn’ and ‘Widersinnig’ (ex. Logical Investigation I, §19; Logical Investigation IV, Introduction,
§12). These words may, however, also be understood in the sense of paradox or
contradiction and paradoxical, contradictory, or illogical. In that case, they
fall into the family of ‘widersprechen’ (to contradict), ‘Widerspruch’
(contradiction), and ‘widersprechend’ and ‘widerspruchsvoll’, two
common German words meaning contradictory. Given the difficulties and the
importance that Husserl accorded to these concepts, I have chosen to leave ‘Widersinn’,
‘Widersinnigkeit’, and ‘widersinnig’ in German. ‘Unsinn’ can be translated as ‘nonsense’ and ‘unsinnig’ as ‘nonsensical’, but I have chosen to leave them in
German where Husserl talked about Widersinnigkeit.
In relation to his
theory of manifolds, in §57 of these lectures, Husserl points out that in the
concrete spheres, the formal limits imposed by forbidding the use of any
factual Widersinn, any widersinnigen, imaginary concepts, acts
as a constraint and hindrance in deductively theorizing work, but that the
marvelous thing about manifolds is that they free us from such prohibitions and
explain why by passing through the imaginary, what is meaningless, must lead,
not to meaningless, but to true results. In speaking of sets in §39, he notes
that even inferential thinking, makes use of widersinnigen presentations to some degree. As an example, he
points out that, although the set-presentation, the totality-presentation, is
for the most part also realized by mathematicians to begin with, it is
nevertheless of no use for argumentation because it involves a Widersinn. Holding fast to the meaning
of totality, he explains, a totality of triangles, a totality of numbers, is
not graspable intuitively and so cannot exist either. Here he was taking up an
issue he had tackled at the end of Chapter 11 of Philosophy of Arithmetic, where he noted that despite the absurdity
of the idea, analogies fostered a tendency to transpose the idea of
constructing a collection for infinite sets, thereby creating what he called a
kind of “imaginary” concept whose anti-logical nature was harmless in everyday
contexts precisely because its inherent contradictoriness was never obvious in
life. This was, he explained there, the case when “All S” was treated as a
closed set. However, he warned, the situation changes when this imaginary
construct is actually carried over into reasoning and influences judgments. It
is clear, he concluded, that from a strictly logical point of view we must not
ascribe anything more to the concept of infinite sets than is actually logically
permissible, and above all not the absurd idea of constructing the actual set.
The German word
‘Evidenz’ is also without a good
equivalent in English. In §30e of Introduction
to Logic and Theory of Knowledge, Lectures 1906/07, Husserl called ‘Evidenz’ “a word for the fact that, as noeticians affirm and prove, there
is a difference between acts that not only think that something is thus and
thus, but are fully certain and aware, in the manner of perspicacious seeing,
of this being and being thus. Therefore, the thing, the state of affairs is
given in insight”. Evidenz, he
maintained, was nothing other than the quality of givenness understood in a
comprehensive way and not just limited to the being of individual real things. We
face the problem of Evidenz when we
come to understanding the correlation of consciousness and object that concerns
all consciousness–even dreaming, hallucinatory, erring consciousness–and we then
ask the closely interrelated questions as to how we come by the existence of
any object in itself at all, how we know that any object at all exists in
reality, where and when an object is truly given to us, how we know that an
object is given and what it means for an object to be given to us. In §67b of
the lectures published here, he teaches that Evidenz is what necessarily
assures us that we are in the possession of truth. He points out that we can
judge without seeing, blindly, routinely, and so on, but only if we judge
insightfully does our judging have objective cognitive value. If we were not
capable of Evidenz, he maintains,
then no talk of truth and science would make any rational sense.
‘Geist’ is another troublesome German word. ‘Mind’ (the faculty of
reasoning and understanding) is a proper, though imperfect, translation for it
in philosophical contexts, and this is particularly so here, because Husserl is
mainly talking about logic and philosophy of science and his lecture course is
meant to be a critique of reason. I have used it and the corresponding
adjective ‘mental’ (of or pertaining to the mind) when it is a matter of the
psycho-physical reality of human beings. However, ‘Geist’ also translates as ‘spirit’ and in these lectures it and its
adjective ‘spiritual’ are appropriate translations when speaking of supra-individual,
immaterial, abstract realities, such as, for example the communal spirit, the
world of the spirit. I have also used it for animals where it is a question of
“an animating or vital principle held to give life to
physical organisms”. My dictionary also defines ‘spirit’ as meaning ghost, the
third person of the Trinity, fairy, sprite, elf, angel, and demon.
It is likewise very difficult
to know how to translate ‘Gemüt’,
which does simply mean mind, but which refers to the emotive, affective
dimension, in contrast to the Verstand
(understanding) and Wille (will).
Dictionaries typically give ‘mind’, ‘soul’,
‘temperament’, ‘feeling’, ‘spirit’,
‘heart’ as translations for ‘Gemüt’,
but most of these words overlap in very complicated ways with other German philosophical
terms such as ‘Seele’ and ‘Geist’. To convey the meaning of ‘Gemüt’ I have usually appealed to
expressions using the adjective ‘inner’.
***
As the years fly by, I grow increasingly grateful for the truly
generous, steadfast support I have received from senior colleagues, who for
decades, year after year, always made themselves available to help me. So once
again I must thank, in alphabetical order: Paul Gochet†, Ivor Grattan-Guinness†,
Jaakko Hintikka†, Ruth Barcan Marcus†, and Dallas Willard†. To the above list I
must add my spiritual director of 24 years Jacques Sommet s.j.†, Barry Smith,
my first philosophy teacher Roger Schmidt, my last philosophy teacher Maurice
Clavelin, and Bernd Magnus†, who in 1970 agreed to direct my Senior Honors Thesis
on Husserl and in 1977 oriented me toward work on Husserl and contemporary
logic. Then one thing led to another…. Thank you.
This
translation was made possible by a fellowship from the National Endowment for
the Humanities in Washington, D. C. I am very grateful to it for its support.
It is dedicated to the
memory of my precursor Dallas Willard.
[1] Cited Hua XXX, p. XXIII, n. 4.
[2] Cited Hua XXX, p. XXIII n. 1.
[3] Johann Wolfgang von Goethe, Faust, Part II, Act I.
[4] Husserl, Edmund, Alte und neue Logik, Vorlesung 1908/09, Dordrecht, Kluwer, 2003, p. 6.
[5]
Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason,
II. Transcendental Doctrine of Method, Chapter 3, The Architectonic of Pure
Reason.
[6] “On
Fundamental Differences between Dependent and Independent Meanings”, Axiomathes, An International Journal in
Ontology and Cognitive Systems 20: 2-3, online since May 29, 2010, 313-32,
(DOI 10.1007/s10516-010-9104-1). “Incomplete Symbols, Dependent Meanings, and
Paradoxes”, in Husserl's Logical
Investigations, Daniel O. Dahlstrom (ed.), Dordrecht, Kluwer, 2003, 69-93.
Both papers are anthologized in Claire Ortiz Hill and Jairo José da Silva, The Road Not Taken, On Husserl’s Philosophy
of Logic and Mathematics, London, College Publications, 2013.
[7] Dagfinn Føllesdal, “Husserl’s
Notion of Noema”, Journal of Philosophy 66 (1969), 680-87.
[8] Claire
Ortiz Hill, Word and Object in Husserl,
Frege, and Russell, the Roots of Twentieth Century Philosophy, Athens, Ohio
University Press, p. 30. The page reference in the text is to Husserl’s Cartesian Meditations, The Hague,
Martinus Nijhoff, 1973, p. 31.
[9]
See his “Foreword II”, Logical
Investigations vol. I, London, Routledge and Kegan Paul, p. 48.
[10] In this regard, it interesting to compare the theory
of noetics expounded in these lectures with his ideas about the “subjective
ideal conditions” making possible the operations of thinking in §§32, 64-65 of
his “Prolegomena to Pure Logic”, the first volume of his Logical Investigations, with his §§25-33 Introduction to Logic and Theory of Knowledge, Lectures
1906/07; and with §94 of Ideas I, where he speaks of noesis and
noema in the sphere of judgment.
[11] See also Claire Ortiz Hill, “Husserl
and Frege on Functions”, Husserl and Analytic Philosophy, Guillermo
Rosado Haddock (ed.), Berlin, de Gruyter, 2016, pp. 89-117.
[12] Edmund
Husserl, Logik, Vorlesung 1896, Dordrecht,
Kluwer, 2001, pp. 272-73 and his Logik,
Vorlesung 1902/03, Dordrecht, Kluwer, 2001, pp. 231, 239-49.
[13] Op. cit., Husserl, Alte und
neue Logik, Vorlesung 1908/09, p.
213.
[14] Translated in my book with
Jairo da Silva, The Road Not Taken, On
Husserl’s Philosophy of Logic and Mathematics cited above, pp. 390-91.
[15] Published in German in G. E.
Rosado Haddock (ed.), Husserl and
Analytic Philosophy, Berlin, de Gruyter, 2016, pp. 289-319. Unfortunately,
Russell’s text is cited (p. 317), but not reproduced there.
[16]
Bertrand Russell, “The Philosophical Implications of Mathematical Logic”, Essays
in Analysis, London, Allen & Unwin, 1973, pp. 292-93.
[17] This is one of the main subjects of my Word and Object in Husserl, Frege and
Russell cited above.
[18] Bertrand Russell, Principles of Mathematics, London,
Norton, 1903, p. 501.
[19] Ibid., p. 502.
[20] Edmund
Husserl, “Psychological Studies in the Elements of Logic”, Early Writings in the Philosophy of Logic and Mathematics,
Dordrecht, Kluwer, 1994, p. 146.
[21] Op. cit., Husserl, Logik, Vorlesung 1902/03, p. 82.
[22] Gottlob Frege, Foundations
of Arithmetic, Blackwell, Oxford, 1884 (1986), §27n.
[23] Op. cit., Husserl, Logik,
Vorlesung 1902/03, p. 56.